Justification, conversation, and folk psychology

  1. Víctor Fernández Castro 1
  1. 1 PSL Research University, Francia
Revista:
Theoria: an international journal for theory, history and foundations of science

ISSN: 0495-4548

Año de publicación: 2019

Volumen: 34

Número: 1

Páginas: 73-88

Tipo: Artículo

DOI: 10.1387/THEORIA.18022 DIALNET GOOGLE SCHOLAR lock_openDialnet editor

Otras publicaciones en: Theoria: an international journal for theory, history and foundations of science

Resumen

El objetivo de este artículo es ofrecer una versión de la hipótesis conversacional sobre conexión ontogenética entre lenguaje y lectura de mentes (Harris 1996, 2005; Van Cleave and Gauker 2010; Hughes et al. 2006). Después de argumentar contra una versión particular de dicha hipótesis (Versión Comunicativa), partiré de la visión justificativa de la cognición social (Andrews 2012; Hutto 2004; Zawidzki 2013) para defender que la función primaria de la adscripción de creencias y deseos es la de justificar y normalizar patrones de comportamiento anormales. Tomando en consideración este marco teórico, argumentaré que el desarrollo de las habilidades de lectura de mentes requiere que los sujetos participen en actividades cooperativas y conjuntas mediadas conversacionalmente gracias a las cuales pueden adquirir la capacidad conceptual de adscribir actitudes proposicionales. Después de presentar la versión general de la hipótesis, se presentan diferentes sub-hipótesis susceptibles de ser testadas y estudios empíricos que las refuerzan

Información de financiación

& I would like to thank Fernando Martínez-Manrique for their valuable comments and suggestions. This paper was written as part of the projects “Inner speech, Metacognition, and the Narrative view of Identity” (FFI2015-65953-P) and “Contemporary Expressivism and the Indispensability of Norma-tive vocabulary” (FFI2016.-80088-P) of the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness.

Financiadores

Referencias bibliográficas

  • Andrews, Kristin. 2009. Understanding norms without a theory of mind. Inquiry 52/5: 433-448.
  • Andrews, Kristin. 2012. Do apes read minds? Toward a new Folk Psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.
  • Astington, Janet W. and Jodie A. Baird. eds. 2005. Why language matters for theory of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Astington, Janet W. and Jennifer M. Jenkins. 1999. A longitudinal study of the relation between language and theory-of-mind development. Developmental psychology 35/5: 1311-1320
  • Astington, Janet W. 2004. Bridging the gap between theory of mind and moral reasoning. In Jodie A. Baird and Bryan W. Sokol, eds., Connections between theory of mind and sociomoral development: No. 103. New directions for child and adolescent development, 63-72. San Francisco, CA: Jossey Bass.
  • Bartsch, Karen and Henry Wellman.1989. Young children’s attribution of action to beliefs and desires. Child Development 60/4: 946-964.
  • Bartsch, Karen and Henry Wellman. 1995. Children talk about the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bermudez, José L. 2003. Thinking without words. Oxford University Press.
  • Brown, Jane N., Nancy Donelan-McCall, and Judy Dunn. 1996. Why talk about mental states? the significance of children’s conversations with friends, siblings, and mothers. Child Development 67/3: 836-849.
  • Carruthers, Peter. 2011. The opacity of mind: an integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Carruthers, Peter. 2013. Mindreading in infancy. Mind and Language 28/2: 141-172.
  • De Villiers, Jill G. 2007. The interface of language and theory of mind. Lingua. International Review of General Linguistics 117/11: 1858-1878.
  • Dunn, Judy. 1994. Changing minds and changing relationships. In Charlie Lewis and Peter Mitchell, eds., Children’s early understanding of mind: Origins and development, 297-310. London: Psychology Press.
  • Dunn, Judy and Jane R. Brown. 1993. Early conversations about causality: Content, pragmatics and developmental change. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 11/2: 107-123.
  • Dunn, Judy and Penny Munn. 1987. Development of justification in disputes with mother and sibling. Developmental Psychology 23/6: 791-798.
  • Dunn, Judy, Jane R. Brown, Cheril Slomkowski, Caroline Tesla, and Leslie Young-blade. 1991. Young children’s understanding of other people’s feelings and beliefs: Individual differences and their antecedents. Child Development 62/6: 1352-1366.
  • Dunn, Judy, Alexadra L. Cutting, & Helen Demetrious. 2000. Moral sensibility, understanding others, and children’s friendship interactions in the preschool period. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 18/2: 159-177.
  • Fernández Castro, Víctor. 2017, online first. Regulation, Normativity and Folk Psychology. Topoi. An International Review of Philosophy. DOI: 10.1007/s11245-017-9511-7.
  • Fodor, Jerry 1992. A theory of the child’s theory of mind. Cognition 44 /3: 283-296.
  • Foote, Rachel C. and Heather A. Holmes-Lonergan. 2003. Sibling conflict and theory of mind. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 21/1: 45-58.
  • Gallagher Shaun 2001. The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8/7-7: 83-108.
  • Gallagher Shaun and Daniel D. Hutto 2008. Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In Jordan Zlatev, Tomothy Racine, Chris Sinha, and Esa Itkonen, eds., The Shared Mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity, 17-38. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
  • Gauker, Christopher. 2003. Words without meaning. Cambridge: MIT Press.
  • Goldman, Alvin I. 2006. Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Gopnik, Alison and Janet W. Astington. 1998. Children’s understanding of representational change and its relation to the understanding of false belief and the appearance-reality distinction. Child Development, 59/1: 26-37.
  • Harris, Peter H. 1996. Desires, beliefs, and language. In Peter Carruthers and Peter K. Smith, eds., Theories of theories of mind, 200-220. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Harris, Peter H. 2005. Conversation, pretense, and theory of mind. In Janet W. Astington and Jodie Baird, eds., Why language matters for theory of mind, 70-83. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Harris, Peter H., Marc Rosnay, and Francisco Pons. 2005. Language and children’s understanding of mental states. Current directions in psychological science 14/2: 69-73.
  • Hughes, Claire and Judy Dunn. 1997. “pretend you didn’t know”: Preschoolers’ talk about mental states in pretend play. Cognitive Development 12/4: 477-497.
  • Hughes, Claire, Keiko K. Fujisawa, Rosie Ensor, Serena Lecce, and Rachel Marfleet. 2006. Cooperation and conversations about the mind: A study of individual differences in 2-year-olds and their siblings. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 24/1: 53-72.
  • Hutto, Daniel D. 2004. The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind and language 19/5: 548-73.
  • Huyder, Vanessa, Elisabeth Nilsen and Sarah Bacso. 2017. The relationship between children’s executive functioning, theory of mind, and verbal skills with their own and others’ behaviour in a cooperative context: Changes in relations from early to middle school-age. Infant and Child Development 26/6.
  • Jenkins, Jennifer J. and Janet W. Astington. 1996. Cognitive factors and family structure associated with theory of mind development in young children. Developmental psychology 32/1: 70-78.
  • Jenkins, Jennifer J. and Janet W. Astington. 2000. Theory of mind and social behavior: Causal models tested in a longitudinal study. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly 46/2: 203-220.
  • Killen, Melanie, Kelly L. Mulvey, Cameron Richardson, Noah Jampol and Amanda Woodward 2011. The Accidental Transgressor: Morally Relevant Theory of Mind. Cognition 119/2: 197-215.
  • Korman, Joanna and Bertram F. Malle. 2016. Grasping for traits or reasons? how people grapple with puzzling social behaviors. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 42/11: 1451-1465.
  • Leslie, Alan M. 1994. Pretending and believing: Issues in the theory of tomm. Cognition 50: 211-238.
  • Lewis, Shevaun, Jeffrey Lidz, and Valentine Hacquard. 2012. The semantics and pragmatics of belief reports in preschoolers. Proceeding Semantics and Linguistic Theory 22: 247-267.
  • Malle, Bertram M., Joshua Knobe, and Sarah Nelson. 2007. Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: New answers to an old question. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93: 491-514.
  • McGeer, Victoria 2001. Psycho-practice, psycho-theory and the contrastive case of autism. how practices of mind become second-nature. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8/5-6: 109-132.
  • McGeer, Victoria 2007. The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In Daniel D. Hutto and Matthew Ratcliffe, eds., Folk Psychology re-assessed, 137-156. Kluwer/Springer Press.
  • McGeer, Victoria 2015. Mind-making practices: The social infrastructure of self- knowing agency and responsibility. Philosophical Explorations 18/2: 259-281.
  • Nichols, Shaun and Stephen Stich. 2003. Mindreading. An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Perner, Josef, Susan R. Leekam and Heinz Wimmer. 1987. Three-year-olds’ difficulty with false belief: The case for a conceptual deficit. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 5/2: 125-137.
  • Perner, Josef, Petra Zauner and Manuel Sprung. 2005. What Does “That” Have to Do with Point of View? Conflicting Desires and “Want” in German. In Janet W. Astington and Jodie Baird, eds., Why language matters for theory of mind, 220-244. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Robinson, Elisabeth J. and Peter Mitchell. 1995. Masking of children’s early understanding of the representational mind: Backwards explanation versus prediction. Child Development 66/4: 1022-1039.
  • Segal, Gabriel (1998). Representing representations. In Peter Carruthers and Jill Boucher, eds., Language and thought, 146-161. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Slomkowski Cheryl L. and Judy Dunn. 1992. Arguments and relationships within the family: Differences in young children’s disputes with mother and sibling. Developmental Psychology 28/5: 919-924.
  • Tanney, Julia. 2013. Rules, reason and self-knowledge. London: Harvard University Press.
  • Tesla, Caroline and Judy Dunn. 1992. Getting along or getting your own way: the development of young children’s use of argument in conflicts with mother and sibling. Social Development 1/2: 107-121.
  • Tooming, Uku. 2016. Mental State Attribution for Interactionism. Studia Philosophica Stonica 9/1: 184-207.
  • Turnbull, Williams, Jeremy Carpendale, and Timothy, O. Racine. 2009. Talk and children’s understanding of mind. Journal of Consciousness Studies 16/6-8: 140-166.
  • Urmson, James O. 1952. Parenthetical verbs. Mind 61/244: 480-496.
  • Uttich, Kevin and Tania Lombrozo. 2010. Norms inform mental state ascriptions: A rational explanation for the side-effect effect. Cognition 116: 87-100.
  • Van Cleave, Matthew and Christopher Gauker. 2010. Linguistic practice and false- belief tasks. Mind and Language 25/3: 298-328.
  • Wellman, Henry R. 2014. Making minds: How theory of mind develops. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wierzbicka, Anna. 2006. English: Meaning and culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wimmer, Heintz and Josef Perner. 1983. Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition 13/1:103-128.
  • Wyman, Emily, Hannes Rakoczy, and Michael Tomasello, M. 2009. Normativity and context in young children’s pretend play. Cognitive Development 24/2: 146-155.
  • Zawidzki, Tadeusz W. 2013. Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press, A Bradford Book.